Aristotle's METAPHYSICS: Book IV (excerpts)
The Study of Fundamental Laws of Thought
We must state whether it belongs to one or to different sciences to inquire
into the truths which are in mathematics called axioms, and into true reality.
Evidently, the inquiry into these also belongs to one science, and that the
science of the philosopher; for these truths hold good for everything that is,
and not merely for some special class of things. Also, all men use them, because
they are true of existing things qua existing thing and each class of things
exists. But men use them just so far as to satisfy their purposes; that is,
as far as the class of things to which their demonstrations refer extends. Therefore
since these truths clearly hold good for all things qua existing things (for
this is what is common to them), the inquiry into these as well belongs to the
inquirer who studies existing things qua existing things.
And for this reason no one who is conducting an inquiry in a specific area tries
to say anything about their truth or falsity--neither the geometer nor the arithmetician.
Some natural philosophers indeed have done so, and their procedure was intelligible
enough; for they thought that they alone were inquiring about the whole of nature
and about existence. But there is a kind of thinker who is above even the natural
philosopher (for nature is only one particular kind of existing thing):...natural
philosophy also is a kind of philosophy, but it is not the first kind.
Evidently then it belongs to the philosopher, i.e. to him who is studying the
nature of all reality, to inquire also into the principles of reasoning. But
he who knows best about each class of things must be able to state the most
certain principles of his subject, so that he whose subject is existing things
qua existing must be able to state the most certain principles of all things.
This is the philosopher.
Characteristics of the Most Fundamental Principle of Knowledge
And the most certain principle of all is that regarding which it is impossible
to be mistaken; for such a principle must be both (a) the best known (for all
men may be mistaken about things which they do not know), and (b) non-hypothetical.
For a principle which every one must have who understands anything that is,
is not a hypothesis; and that which every one must know who knows anything,
he must already have when he comes to a special study. Evidently then such a
principle is the most certain of all.
The Most Fundamental Principle of Knowledge: The Law of Non-Contradiction
[LNC]
Which principle this is, let us proceed to say. It is this: the same attribute
cannot at the same time belong and not belong to the same subject and in the
same respect--we must presuppose, to guard against dialectical objections,
any further qualifications which might be added.
This, then, is the most certain of all principles, since it answers to the definition
given above. For it is impossible for any one to believe the same thing to be
and not to be, as some think Heraclitus says. For what a man says, he does not
necessarily believe; and if (1) it is impossible that contrary attributes should
belong at the same time to the same subject (the usual qualifications must be
presupposed in this premise too), and if (2) an opinion which contradicts another
is contrary to it, then obviously (3) it is impossible for the same man at the
same time to believe the same thing to be and not to be; for if a man were mistaken
on this point he would have contrary opinions at the same time....
Aristotle on ("Heraclitean") Critics of the Law of Non-Contradiction
There are some who, as we said, both themselves assert that it is possible for
the same thing to be and not to be true, and say that people can believe this
to be the case. But we have just now assumed that it is impossible for anything
at the same time to be and not to be the case, and by this means have shown
that this is the most indisputable of all principles.
Some indeed demand that even this principle shall be demonstrated, but they
do this through want of education, for not to know of what things one should
demand demonstration, and of what one should not, argues want of education.
For it is impossible that there should be demonstration of absolutely everything
(there would be an infinite regress, so that there would still be no demonstration);
but if there are things of which one should not demand demonstration, these
persons could not say what principle they maintain to be more evident than the
present one.
We can, however, demonstrate dialectically even that this view is impossible,
if our opponent will only say something; and if he says nothing, it is absurd
to seek to give an argument [logos] for our views to one who cannot give
an statement [logos] about anything, in so far as he cannot do so. For
such a man, as such, is from the start no better than a vegetable.
Now dialectical demonstration I distinguish from demonstration proper, because
in offering a demonstration [of LNC] one might be thought to be begging the
question; but if another person is responsible for the assumption we shall have
dialectical refutation, not demonstration.
The starting-point for all such arguments is not the demand that our opponent
shall say that something either is or is not true (for this one might perhaps
take to be a begging of the question), but that he shall say something which
is significant both for himself and for another; for this is necessary, if he
really is to say anything. For, if he means nothing, such a man will not be
capable of discourse, either with himself or with another. But if any one does
do this, then [dialectical] demonstration will be possible; for we shall already
have something definite. The person responsible for the proof, however, is not
he who demonstrates but he who listens; for while disowning reason he listens
to reason. Moreover, he who admits this has admitted that something is true
apart from demonstration (so that not everything will be 'so and not so').
Aristotle's Refutation of Critics of LNC
Some people have acquired this opinion as other paradoxical opinions have been
acquired; when men cannot refute sophistical arguments, they give in to the
argument and agree that the conclusion is true. This, then, is why some express
this view; others do so because they demand a reason for everything. And the
starting-point in dealing with all such people is definition. Now the definition
rests on the necessity of their meaning something; for the form of words of
which the word is a sign will be its definition....
First then this at least is obviously true, that the word 'be' or 'not be' has
a definite meaning, so that not everything will be 'so and not so'. Again, if
'man' has one meaning, let this be 'two-footed animal' (by having one meaning
I understand this: if 'man' means 'X', then, if A is a man, 'X' will be what
'being a man' means for him).
(It makes no difference even if one were to say a word has several meanings,
if only they are limited in number; for to each definition there might be assigned
a different word. For instance, we might say that 'man' has not one meaning
but several, one of which would have one definition, viz. 'two-footed animal',
while there might be also several other definitions if only they were limited
in number; for a special name might be assigned to each of the definitions.
If, however, they were not limited but one were to say that the word has an
infinite number of meanings, obviously discourse would be impossible; for not
to have one meaning is to have no meaning, and if words have no meaning intelligible
discourse with one another, and indeed with ourselves, has been annihilated;
for it is impossible to think of anything if we do not think of one thing; but
if this is possible, one name might be assigned to this thing.)
Let it be assumed then, as was said at the beginning, that the name has a meaning
and has one meaning; it is impossible, then, that 'being a man' should mean
precisely 'not being a man', if 'man' not only signifies something about one
subject but also has one significance (for we do not identify 'having one significance'
with 'signifying something about one subject', since on that assumption even
'intelligent' and 'tall' and 'man' would have had one significance, so that
all things would have been one; for they would all have had the same significance).
And it will not be possible to be and not to be the same thing, except in virtue
of an ambiguity, just as if one whom we call 'man', others were to call 'not-man';
but the point in question is not this, whether the same thing can at the same
time be and not be a man in name, but whether it can in fact. Now if 'man' and
'not-man' mean nothing different, obviously 'not being a man' will mean nothing
different from 'being a man'; so that 'being a man' will be 'not being a man';
for they will be one. For being one means this: being related as 'clothes' and
'dress' are, if their definition is one. And if 'being a man' and 'being a not-man'
are to be one, they must mean one thing. But it was shown earlier' that they
mean different things. Therefore, if it is true to say of anything that it is
a man, it must be a two-footed animal (for this was what 'man' meant); and if
this is necessary, it is impossible that the same thing should not at that time
be a two-footed animal; for this is what 'being necessary' means--that it is
impossible for the thing not to be. It is, then, impossible that it should be
at the same time true to say the same thing is a man and is not a man.
A Further (Pragmatic) Argument against the "Heracliteans"
It is in the highest degree evident that neither any one of those who maintain
this view nor any one else is really in this position. For why does a man walk
to Megara and not stay at home, when he thinks he ought to be walking there?
Why does he not walk early some morning into a well or over a precipice, if
one happens to be in his way? Why do we observe him guarding against this, evidently
because he does not think that falling in is alike good and not good? Evidently,
then, he judges one thing to be better and another worse. And if this is so,
he must also judge one thing to be a man and another to be not-a-man, one thing
to be sweet and another to be not-sweet. For he does not aim at and judge all
things alike, when, thinking it desirable to drink water or to see a man, he
proceeds to aim at these things; yet he ought, if the same thing were alike
a man and not-a-man. But, as was said, there is no one who does not obviously
avoid some things and not others. Therefore, as it seems, all men make unqualified
judgements, if not about all things, still about what is better and worse. And
if this is not knowledge but opinion, they should be all the more anxious about
the truth, as a sick man should be more anxious about his health than one who
is healthy; for he who has opinions is, in comparison with the man who knows,
not in a healthy state as far as the truth is concerned....
Aristotle on Protagorean Relativism
From the same opinion proceeds the doctrine of Protagoras, and both doctrines
must be alike true or alike untrue. For on the one hand, if all opinions and
appearances are true, all statements must be at the same time true and false.
For many men hold beliefs in which they conflict with one another, and think
those mistaken who have not the same opinions as themselves; so that the same
thing must both be and not be the case.
And on the other hand, if this is so, all opinions must be true; for those who
are mistaken and those who are right are opposed to one another in their opinions;
if, then, reality is such as the view in question supposes, all will be right
in their beliefs.
Evidently, then, both doctrines proceed from the same way of thinking. But the
same method of discussion must not be used with all opponents; for some need
to have their beliefs changed, and others require the compulsion of proof. Those
who have been driven to this position by difficulties in their thinking can
easily be cured of their ignorance; for it is not their expressed argument but
their thought that one has to meet. But those who argue for the sake of argument
can be cured only by refuting the argument as expressed in speech and in words.
Those who really feel the difficulties have been led to this opinion by observation
of the sensible world.
(1) They think that contradictories or contraries are true at the same time,
because they see contraries coming into existence out of the same thing. If,
then, that which is not cannot come to be, the thing must have existed before
as both contraries alike, as Anaxagoras says all is mixed in all.
[In response to (1)] To those, then, whose belief rests on these grounds, we
shall say that in a sense they speak rightly and in a sense they err. For 'that
which is' has two meanings, so that in some sense a thing can come to be out
of that which is not, while in some sense it cannot, and the same thing can
at the same time be in being and not in being--but not in the same respect.
For the same thing can be potentially at the same time two contraries,
but it cannot actually be so. Moreover, we shall ask them to believe
that among existing things there is also another kind of substance to which
neither movement nor destruction nor generation at all belongs.
(2) Similarly some have inferred from observation of the sensible world the
truth of appearances. For they think that the truth should not be determined
by the large or small number of those who hold a belief, and that the same thing
is thought sweet by some when they taste it, and bitter by others, so that if
all were ill or all were mad, and only two or three were well or sane, these
would be thought ill and mad, and not the others.
They also say that many of the other animals receive impressions contrary to
ours; and that even to the senses of each individual, things do not always seem
the same. Which, then, of these impressions are true and which are false is
not obvious; for the one set is no more true than the other, but both are alike.
And this is why Democritus, at any rate, says that either there is no truth
or to us at least it is not evident....
And it is in this direction that the consequences are most troublesome. For
if those who have seen most of such truth as is possible for us (and these are
those who seek and love it most [i.e. philosophers])--if these have such opinions
and express these views about the truth, is it not natural that beginners in
philosophy should lose heart? For to seek the truth would be a wild goose chase.
And again, (3) because they saw that all this world of nature is in movement
and that about that which changes no true statement can be made, they said that
of course, regarding that which everywhere in every respect is changing, nothing
could truly be affirmed. It was this belief that blossomed into the most extreme
of the views above mentioned, that of the professed Heracliteans, such as was
held by Cratylus, who finally did not think it right to say anything but only
moved his finger, and criticized Heraclitus for saying that it is impossible
to step twice into the same river; for he thought one could not do it even once....
[In response to (3)] But let us insist on this, that it is not the same thing
to change in quantity and in quality. Grant that in quantity a thing is not
constant; still it is in respect of its form that we know each thing.
And again, it would be fair to criticize those who hold this view for asserting
about the whole material universe what they saw only in a minority even of sensible
things. For only that region of the sensible world which immediately surrounds
us is always in process of destruction and generation; but this is--in a word--not
even a fraction of the whole, so that it would have been juster to acquit this
part of the world because of the other part, than to condemn the other because
of this....
[In response to (2)] Again, it is fair to express surprise at our opponents'
raising the question whether magnitudes are as great, and colors are of such
a nature, as they appear to people at a distance, or as they appear to those
close at hand, and whether they are such as they appear to the healthy or to
the sick, and whether those things are heavy which appear so to the weak or
those which appear so to the strong, and those things true which appear to the
sleeping or to the waking. For obviously they do not think these to be open
questions; no one, at least, if when he is in Libya he has fancied one night
that he is in Athens, starts for the concert hall.
Further Responses to Protagorean Relativism
Moreover, with regard to the future, as Plato says [in the Theaetetus],
surely the opinion of the physician and that of the ignorant man are not equally
weighty, for instance, on the question whether a man will get well or not.
And again...the same wine might seem, if either it or one's body changed, at
one time sweet and at another time not sweet; but at least sweetness,
such as it is when it exists, has never yet changed, but one is always right
about it, and what it is to be sweet is of necessity of such and such a nature.
Yet all these views destroy this necessity, leaving nothing to be of necessity,
as they leave no essence of anything; for the necessary cannot be in this way
and also in that, so that if anything is of necessity, it will not be 'both
so and not so'.
And, in general, if only the sensible exists, there would be nothing if animate
things were not; for there would be no faculty of sense. Now the view that neither
the sensible qualities nor the sensations would exist is doubtless true (for
they are affections of the perceiver), but that the substrata which cause the
sensation should not exist even apart from sensation is impossible. For sensation
is surely not the sensation of itself, but there is something beyond the sensation,
which must be prior to the sensation; for that which moves is prior in nature
to that which is moved, and if they are correlative terms, this is no less the
case.
[In response to (2)] There are, both among those who have these convictions
and among those who merely profess these views for the sake of argument, some
who raise a difficulty by asking, who is to be the judge of the healthy man,
and in general who is likely to judge rightly on each class of questions?
But such inquiries are like puzzling over the question whether we are now asleep
or awake. And all such questions have the same force. These people demand that
a reason shall be given for everything; for they seek a starting-point, and
they seek to get this by demonstration, while it is obvious from their actions
that they have no conviction. But their mistake is what we have stated it to
be; they seek a reason for things for which no reason can be given; for the
starting-point of demonstration is not demonstration.
These, then, might be easily persuaded of this truth, for it is not difficult
to grasp; but those who seek merely compulsion in argument seek what is impossible;
for they demand to be shown that they contradict themselves--a claim which [given
their view that contradictory statements can both be true at the same time]
contradicts their own position from the start.
But if not all things are relative, but some are self-existent, not everything
that appears will be true; for that which appears is apparent to some one; so
that he who says all things that appear are true, makes all things relative.
And, therefore, those who ask for an irresistible argument, and at the same
time demand to be shown that their views are false, must guard themselves by
saying that the truth is not that what appears exists, but that what appears
is true for him to whom it appears, and when, and to the sense to which,
and under the conditions under which it appears.
And if they give an account of their view, but do not give it in this way, they
will soon find themselves contradicting themselves. For to those who for the
reasons named some time ago say that what appears is true, and therefore that
all things are alike false and true, for things do not appear either the same
to all men or always the same to the same man, but often have contrary appearances
at the same time (for touch says there are two objects when we cross our fingers,
while sight says there is one)--to these we shall say 'yes, but not to the same
sense and in the same part of it and under the same conditions and at the same
time', so that what appears will be with these qualifications true. But perhaps
for this reason those who argue thus not because they feel a difficulty but
for the sake of argument, should say that this is not true, but true for
this man. And as has been said before, they must make everything relative
-- relative to opinion and perception, so that nothing either has come to be
or will be without some one's first thinking so. But if things have come to
be or will be in that way, evidently not all things will be relative to opinion.
Aristotle's Conclusion
Let this, then, suffice to show (1) that the most indisputable of all beliefs
is that contradictory statements are not at the same time true, and (2) what
consequences follow from the assertion that they are, and (3) why people do
assert this....
Examine whole text (W.D. Ross translation) HERE