The Principle of Clarity
Although reasoning is something that you can
do in the relative privacy of your own mind, it is more commonly
an act of communication. Usually it is to others that we
justify our beliefs and with others that we attempt to
understand the world. As such, reasoning is a cooperative
undertaking that requires clarity on the part of those who
supply it, and charity on the part of those who receive it. So
far we have focused on the importance of charity as a guide to
the reconstruction and evaluation of rationales. We now turn to
the importance of clarity in the actual formulation and
presentation of reasoning.
Like the Principle of Charity, the
Principle of Clarity can be formulated in the language of the
Golden Rule: Reason unto others as you would have them
reason unto you. But, again just likr yhe Principle of
Charity, this formulation works only for those who are
comfortable approaching reasoning from a logical point of view.
Someone who reasons "You should wear the black dress. The one
you're wearing makes you look a lot fatter than you are," is
quite a bit clearer than someone who reasons "That's a really
pretty dress, but maybe you should wear the black one tonight
instead. It is so sexy. " But there are times in life
when tact, not clarity is the most important thing.
(Philosophers don't always get that.)
It is worth noting here that while we will
usually speak of clarity as a presentational virtue and charity
as an interpretive virtue, both principles really aim at the
same thing. To be charitable is to provide the clearest possible
interpretation; to be clear is to reason in a way that
facilitates charitable interpretation. So the Principle of
Charity and the Principle of Clarity are just two ways of
expressing a more fundamental commitment to rational
communication and inquiry.
Exploiting Context: Innuendo
Human beings have an extraordinary ability
to communicate things that they don't actually say. Of course,
other animals are good at this, too, since they communicate
without saying anything at all. But we are unique in that we
can use language to communicate things that we don't
say. This is actually a nice way to understand the purpose of
implication. Because we are able to detect logical
relationships, we are able to draw conclusions that are
logically implied, but not stated. For example:
- Simone: I
busted my hump cleaning the house this morning and when I left
here this place was spotless. Someone really did a number on
this place, and you Steven are the only one who has been here
all day.
- Steven:
So, what are you trying to say?
Short of explicitly ruling out the
possibility that the house messed itself up, Simone has given
Dirk all the information he needs to understand that Simone
believes Dirk messed up the house. Her statements, properly
interpreted, logically imply this. But we rarely need to be
this explicit. We can get people to draw conclusions that are
neither stated nor logically implied, but merely suggested. For
example:
- Mom: Rachel,
you were out awfully late last night. I hope you weren't at
Vinny's again. You know how your father and I disapprove of
him.
- Rachel: Mom, I
swear, I was not at Vinny's. When are you going to start
trusting me. I went to the movies with Bruce.
- Mom: Bruce?
Oh, that's great. I really like Bruce.
Notice that Rachel has just convinced her
mom that she wasn't with Vinny even though she didn't say that
or anything that strictly implied that. Now, as you probably
realize, the truth is that she was with Vinny. She and
her friend Lynn went with Vinny and Bruce to the movies, and
later on they went back to Lynn's house, where Rachel had
precisely the sort of interaction with Vinny that her mother is
concerned about.
If Rachel feels any guilt about how she
answered her mother's question, she may seek consolation in the
fact that she didn't literally lie to her. After all,
Mom asked if Rachel was at Vinny's house, not if she was
with Vinny. And Rachel did, in a sense, go to the movies with
Bruce (after all, he was there), it just so happens that she was
with Vinny. Of course, if Rachel is honest with herself
she will realize that whether she calls it lying or not, she
certainly deceived her mother. She did so by taking advantage
of a context in which it was perfectly reasonable to conclude
from what Rachel said that she had not been with Vinny at all.
To understand what Rachel in logical terms
we introduce the following logical fallacy:
Innuendo
- Definition:
Exploiting contextual assumptions to suggest a conclusion that
has been neither stated nor logically implied, when there are
reasons for doubting that one would be willing to claim it
explicitly.
- MOI:
Identify the suggested conclusion, showing how, in the given
context, it might be reasonably inferred despite the fact that
it was neither stated nor implied. Give reasons for doubting
that it's author would claim it explicitly.
People like Rachel often commit the
fallacy of innuendo on purpose, which means that they are
purposely trying to get others to believe something that has
been neither stated nor implied. However, strictly
speaking the fallacy doesn't require people to do this
intentionally. Rather, it just requires them to use
language so unclearly that it has this effect.
Let's look at a couple of more examples of
innuendo.
Example 1
- Frieda: Melanie
this meat is really tender! Did you that a car ran over your
Chihuahua yesterday?
Analysis: This is an
innuendo. Without saying so, Melanie suggests the
conclusion that they are eating Frieda's dead dog. This is
obviously a (gross) joke, which is why she wouldn't claim
explicitly that they were eating Frieda's dog.
Rachel succeeded in obfuscating her
relationship with Vinny in two ways.
First, she took advantage of the
context by making claims that were literally true, but which
suggested things that were actually false; i.e., it is true that
she was not at Vinny's house, but in the context, this suggested
the false conclusion that she was not with Vinny at all.
Second, she made statements whose
truth depended on certain words being interpreted in a way that
was not appropriate to the context; i.e., Rachel said that she
had been "with" Bruce in a context that suggested that she had
been with Bruce in particular rather than merely traveling in
the same group. (Rachel's vegetarian joke also traded on using
the phrase "have for dinner" in a way that was different than
her mom intended, though this didn't contribute to the
obfuscation.)
These two ways of taking advantage of
unstated contextual assumptions can be formalized as follows.
Example 1
- Frieda: Melanie
this meat is really tender! Did you that a car ran over your
Chihuahua yesterday?
Analysis: Without saying
so, Melanie suggests the conclusion that they are eating
Frieda's dead dog.
Example 2
- Frieda: Did you
know that Martha and I are the only ones who are getting an A
in logic?
- Melanie: No, I
didn't know that, but it sure doesn't surprise me that you
guys are getting exactly the same grade, since you always seem
to get exactly the same score on all of your assignments.
Analysis: This is a
straightforward case of Melanie insinuating, without claiming
explicitly, that Melanie is getting an A in logic because she
copies Martha's assignments, or vice versa.
Example 3
-
Frankie Roberts, Jr. was like so many teenagers in our
community. He was active in sports, popular with classmates,
and was adored by his parents. Often called a “gentle
giant” by those who loved him, Frankie was known for his
kindness and commitment to being a successful adult.
Tragically, Frankie was also like so many teens in our
community because he abused steroids, and last year, at the
age of 19, the beautiful young man took his life trying to
withdraw from the deadly drug.
Analysis: This is an innuendo because it suggests
without saying so that the effects of withdrawal from steroids
was the primary reason for Frankie's suicide. The author
should either say so explicitly, or provide straightforward
reasons for thinking this is a common effect.
It is
important to be cautious in accusing someone of committing an
innuendo. Because we often do not say things we really do
mean, it can seem as if we are committing innuendo when we are
not. For example, if you said that you had dinner at
Lenny's last night, that strongly suggests that you had dinner
with Lenny himself. Unless (as in the Rachel case above) I
have some reasons for thinking that you did not have dinner with
Lenny, I should not be suspecting you of committing innuendo
when you say this.
Example 4
- Helena:
Melissa, do you still seriously wonder whether men find you
attractive? That guy just held the door open for you when you
were still 30 feet away, and then practically wet himself when
you winked at him.
Analysis : This may seem like an
innuendo, because it strongly suggests that men find Melissa
attractive without actually saying it. But Helena clearly is
saying that men do find Melissa attractive, so it does
not really conform to the definition. It is important to
understand that we often suggest things that we really would
state explicitly, just because suggestion is more fun, or
explicit statement is deemed unnecessary. (Note, that you
might say that there is an innuendo here that blondes are
stupid.)
The Fallacy of Equivocation
Another common way of violating the
principle of clarity is to equivocate on the meaning of a word
or phrase. To understand what we mean here, let's revisit an
example that we earlier identified as both an ad hominem and a
straw man..
-
Jesus Christ, I am just
sick of that Reverend Tom Baxter preaching to us about love.
Love thy neighbor! Love thy enemies! Love thy
neighborhood child molester! After that affair he had
with Wilma Barrington last year you'd think he might realize
that lovin' your neighbor's wife just ain't a particularly
bright idea.
Recall that the straw man aspect of this
example relies on using the word 'love' in two different ways.
Tom Baxter is not encouraging his congregation to become
romantically involved with their neighbors and enemies, but what
the speaker is saying only makes sense if he attributes that
meaning to the preacher.
Here is the formal definition of
equivocation.
Equivocation
- Definition: Using a word or
expression in a sense that is alien to the given context
without adequate notice or justification.
- Identification: Identify the
word or expression in question and identify the two different
senses that have been equivocated upon: (1) the sense that
would normally be assumed in the given context and (2) the
sense that is being assigned without adequate notice or
justification.
Here are a few examples of equivocation.
Example 1
- Melanie: I
enjoy doing art.
- Frieda: That's
nice. And does Art enjoy doing you?
Analysis
Two words have been equivocated upon:
"doing" and "art". Melanie uses the terms to express her
enjoyment of artistic activities. Frieda assigned different
meanings to suggest that what Melanie was expressing was her
satisfying sexual activities with a man named Art.
Example 2
- Frieda: That
was Martha. Did you know that Martha truly believes that
Derrick is in love with her?
- Melanie: Wow,
Sammy is going to be upset. Aren't Sammy and Derrick like
practically engaged?
- Frieda: Yeah,
but Sammy won't be upset. It's no skin off her nose.
- Melanie: What
do you mean. I'd be upset if Lennny was two-timing me.
- Frieda: What?
Derrick isn't two-timing Sammy.
- Melanie: You
just said Derrick is in love with Martha.
- Frieda: No I
didn't! I said Martha believes that.
- Melanie: You
said she believes it and that it's true.
- Frieda. No, I
said she truly believes that.
- Melanie:
Right! So it's true.
- Frieda: No,
she just really, sincerely believes it!
- Melanie: Oh,
well, you should have said that.
Analysis
This is an example of equivocation
on the phrase "truly believes". Frieda uses the phrase to
mean "sincerely believes" but Melanie understands it to mean
"has a true belief that".
Of course, this is not a very serious
example. It's more of a comedy of errors in the tradition of
Abbot and Costello's
Who's on First? Although for us it does serve as
another illustration of the difference between asserting that
someone believes something and asserting that what they
believe is true. And, in fact, the equivocal meaning of the
phrase "truly believe" is easily exploited to give specious
plausibility to certain sincerely held beliefs for which there
is actually very little evidence.
Example 3
- Francine:
Well, I'm sorry you got into an accident, but you're
definitely the one whose legally responsible for it. You
rear-ended the guy while you were talking on your cell-phone.
- Vanna: I am not
responsible! He slammed on his breaks just to avoid a
friggin' squirrel!
Analysis: This example
equivocates on the term 'responsible'. Francine
said that Vanna is legally responsible for the accident.
Vanna seems to be claiming that she is not causally or morally
responsible.
Example 4
Jokes often depend on equivocation.
For example:
-
Two hunters are out in the woods when one of them collapses.
He doesn't seem to be breathing and his eyes are glazed. The
other guy whips out his cell phone and calls the emergency
services. He gasps, "My friend is dead! What can I do?". The
operator says "Calm down. I can help. First, let's make sure
he's dead." There is a silence, then a shot is heard. Back on
the phone, the guy says "OK, now what?"
Analysis
This
joke equivocates on the phrase "make sure". In one sense
"make sure" means "verify". In the other sense it means
"cause".
You may be interested to know that this
joke won an international contest to determine the funniest joke
in the world.
Here is another example:
Example 5
-
Two TV antennas met on a roof, fell in love and got
married. The ceremony was boring as hell but the
reception was incredible.
Analysis: This joke equivocates on the word
'reception'. The two meanings are "celebration after a
wedding" and "resolution of a radio signal".
Example 6
- Melanie: Is
something wrong? You've really been acting different lately.
- Frieda: What
are you trying to say? I thought being different is what you
liked about me.
This example contains
both equivocation and innuendo.
Analysis 1
Frieda equivocates on
the term "different." Melanie originally used the term to
mean that Frieda's behavior has changed. Frieda's response
shows that she has interpreted Melanie's remark as a complaint
that Frieda is different from other people.
Analysis 2
Frieda's hypersensitive
response also contains an innuendo because it suggests,
without implying or claiming explicitly, that Melanie is
criticizing her unfairly, and that perhaps it is really
Melanie who has changed. It is not clear that Frieda would
claim this explicitly, since her only basis for saying it is
her own misinterpretation of an expression of concern for a
criticism.
And here is an example that may appear to
be an equivocation, but really is not.
Example 6
- It was probably
inevitable that Barack Obama's speech on race would be
dissected during another race, the race for the U.S.
presidency.
IAnalysis
This example may appear to commit
equivocation but it does not. Here, the author clearly and
intentionally uses the term 'race' in two different sense.
But she does this just to be cute. Nobody who understands
English will confuse one usage with the other. It is
important to remember that equivocation occurs as a fallacy
only when the meanings of the words or expressions are
actually being conflated.
|