ROBERT WENDLAND’S NON-SUICIDAL
INTENTION
In
a fairly substantial piece I am writing on Robert Wendland I state that the
Amici Curiae brief submitted to the California Supreme Court supporting his
extubation was badly written due to its
adversarial legal setting and poorly informed by traditional Catholic medical
ethics in spite of several “Catholic”
institutional undersigners. My review of the
Court's decision notes that it saw this case as a request to kill a conscious patient who was not even sick, who was making limited
progress, and who would be likely to suffer distress, since he was conscious,
from the prolonged process of dehydration. I suggest further that the Court may
very well been aware that claiming that such an action was a legitimate "letting
die" of a dying patient would sound like nonsense to objective observers.
And worse than nonsense, it would be open to the kind of plea that James
Rachels makes that active killing would be more merciful. (Rachels' piece has
been reprinted in most college texts on this issue.)
My judgment of the case, as
framed by the Court's language, is obviously negative about the Amici Curiae
brief and completely in agreement with the Court.
There
is, however, a question left unanswered:
If Robert Wendland had been less cognitively disabled would he have been
suicidal if he asked to have all the technology removed? My answer is that in
judging his own case he can choose any probable opinion and the following I
take to be a probable non-suicidal application of the principle of double
-effect to his case: Robert Wendland could say to himself: "I was severely
injured in my accident and the medical interventions imposed on me while I was
unconscious had a good purpose--to provide time to see if I would recover. They
arrested a dying process and removed the danger of dying inherent in my
inability to eat while unconscious. Now that I am conscious it appears to me
that these technologies cannot aid my recovery. I remain in a state of
"arrested dying" where the life I have is essentially an artifact of
technology, a human creation, which could be called a "fabricated
life." Its fabrication does not make it a bad life, but it does make it a
continual production of human skill. It is a basic moral principle that we are
responsible for what we create by our technology and have not only the right
but the obligation to judge its balance of benefits and harms. In this case the
judgment is whether the harm prevented by the group of medical technologies(my death) is greater than the unintended but
obvious and unavoidable harm of its side effects. The side effects are
the unnatural and unbearable conditions which these technologies impose on me.
These conditions outweigh the harm of losing the fabricated life the technologies
are meant to provide. The conditions are worse than the death which will occur
when I decline the technologies. In declining them I am not seeking or
intending my death. The vulnerability to death which will occur upon their
removal is due to the original trauma (the "underlying cause of
dying") which I did not intend, and which I would reverse if I could do so
without such serious harm to my person--the serious harm of the conditions the
technologies impose on me. I merely accept that death and reject the
technologies since they do me no good in the balance."
My comment on this reasoning is
that it contains two applications of the principle of double-effect. One in
which the deliberate action being judged is the imposition of the medical
technologies for the sake of providing a fabricated life (which is different
from healing), and in the second the deliberate action is the decision to order
removed from oneself the medical technologies for the sake of being rid of
their excessive pain, distress and mental costs. Robert could reasonably go on
to say: "That a side effect of this action will be that I will lose the
fabricated life is something that I accept. I am not acting in rebellion
against God or nature since neither God nor nature is
the author of this fabricated life and certainly not of the excessive pain,
distress and mental suffering it brings with it. It was something invented by
medical science and for me it has no good purpose. So I reject it."
Our normal abhorrence of
"quality of life" considerations in judging life-preserving
technologies is based on a distinctly Judeo-Christian conviction of the
sacredness of life, even when seriously reduced by disease or trauma, such as
we see in the victims of serious stroke. But in those cases we need to decide
whether the low quality of life is simply an abiding injury while the body
itself, with some help, carries out the normal self-therapeutic functions of
nutrition, metabolism, respiration, fighting off infection and so forth. As
each of these is replaced by a technological intervention we approach admitting
that the life is a fabrication, not the sacred gift of God, but the product of
human technology and therefore open to judgment. There is no moral slippery
slope in this argument, but only the vagueness of the distinction between a
natural, but diminished and self-sustaining life, and a fabricated life.
Indeed, if we do not allow and actually require this kind of judgment on
"fabricated life" we run the risk of another slippery slope, namely a
slide into the claim that biological life is to be maintained at any and all
costs including Frankensteinian impositions on hapless patients.
It is fortunate that the legal
right to refuse medical intervention preserves competent patients' right to
select any probable opinion about the moral rightness of their rejection of
medical interventions. But the Court made clear that what it was refusing
to accept was not any of the careful distinctions about non-suicidal or
non-killing intentions at all. It was refusing to accept the intentional
killing of a patient who was not dying. My representation of Robert's probable
opinion was that he judges his state to be one of unsuccessful (due to
unacceptable side effects) arrested dying, and that his decision is to reject
the unsuccessful technologies, not to kill himself.
Finally, it is interesting that
the Court, probably innocent of any knowledge of the distinctions of
"probablism" (to which Robert is entitled) and "tutiorism"
(to which third parties are obliged) concluded by explicitly using a
"safer-course" reasoning to impose a "safest course"
standard of proof.